Skip to main content

24 Donnelly on Slavery in Saudi Arabia

24  Donnelly on Slavery in Saudi Arabia

Jack Donnelly, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, Third Edition (Cornell University Press, 2013)


To intervene or not to intervene, that is the question.


“Suppose that in contemporary Saudi Arabia a group were to emerge arguing that because slavery was accepted in the early Muslim world it should be reinstituted in contemporary Saudi Arabia. I am certain that most Saudis, from the most learned clerics to the most ordinary citizens, would reject this view. How, though, should this group be dealt with?

So long as these fundamentalists do not attempt to practice slavery, dialogue--including harsh criticism by both Saudis and foreigners--seems to [115] me the appropriate route. Those in the majority have, I think, a moral obligation to use the most forceful possible terms. Nonetheless, freedom of belief and speech requires the majority to tolerate these views, in the minimal sense of not imposing legal liabilities on those who hold or express them. Should they attempt to practice slavery, however, it would be entirely appropriate, and probably even demanded, that the force of the law be applied to suppress and punish it.

Suppose, though, that the unthinkable were to occur and the practice of slavery were reintroduced in Saudi Arabia--not, let us imagine, as a matter of law, but rather through the state refusing to prosecute slave-holders. Here we run up against the state system and the fact that international human rights law gives states near total discretion to implement internationally recognized human rights within their own territories. Although one might argue that slavery is legally prohibited as a matter of jus cogens , general principles of law, and both customary law and treaties, coercive international enforcement would be, at best, extraordinarily contentious and without much legal precedent. Outsiders, however, remain bound by their own moral principles (as well as by international human rights norms) to condemn such practices in the strongest possible terms and foreign states would be entirely justified in putting whatever pressure short of force they could mobilize on Saudi Arabia to halt the practice.

This hypothetical example illustrates the fact that some cultural practices demand our condemnation rather than our respect. It also, however, indicates that some beliefs, although despicable, demand our toleration--because freedom of opinion and belief is an internationally recognized human right. So long as one stays within the limits of internationally recognized human rights, one is entitled to at least a limited and grudging toleration, and the personal space that comes with that.

Many cases, however, are not so “easy,” especially where change is substantial or unusually rapid. In much of the global South—and pockets of the developed world as well--we regularly face the problem of “modern” individuals or groups who reject traditional practices. Should we give priority to the idea of community self-determination and permit the enforcement of customary practices against modern “deviants,” even if this violates “universal” human rights? Or should individual self-determination prevail, thus sanctioning claims of universal human rights against traditional society?”

Comments

Popular posts from this blog

29 Donnelly on Misunderstanding Culture

29   Donnelly on Misunderstanding Culture Jack Donnelly, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice , Third Edition (Cornell University Press, 2013) “Consider the common claim that Asian societies are communitarian and consensual whereas Western societies are individualistic and competitive. What exactly is this supposed to explain? . . .  Culture does much less explanatory work than most relativists suggest–at least that the ‘culture’ in question is more local or national than regional or a matter of civilization” (97). “Substantive cultural relativism risks reducing ‘right’ to ‘traditional.’ ‘Good’ to ‘old,’ and ‘obligatory’ to ‘habitual.’ Few societies or individuals, however, believe that their values are binding simply or even princiapply because they happen to be widely endorsed within their culture” (109). “Cultural relativism is particularly problematic when it presents culture as coherent, homogeneous, consensual, and static. In fact, though, differences within cult

15 Who was Wesley Hohfeld?

Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld (9 August 1879, Oakland, California – 21 October 1918, Alameda, California)[1] was an American jurist. He was the author of the seminal Fundamental Legal Conceptions as Applied in Judicial Reasoning and Other Legal Essays (1919). During his life he published only a handful of law journal articles. After his death the material forming the basis of Fundamental Legal Conceptions was derived from two articles in the Yale Law Journal (1913) and (1917) that had been partially revised with a view to publication. Editorial work was undertaken to complete the revisions and the book was published with the inclusion of the manuscript notes that Hohfeld had left, plus seven other essays. The work remains a powerful contribution to modern understanding of the nature of rights and the implications of liberty. To reflect Hohfeld's continuing importance, a chair at Yale University is named after him. The chair is currently occupied by Gideon

6 Rights: Categories & Analysis of Rights (SEP) by Leif Wenar

6   “Rights” by Leif Wenar ( Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy) 1. Categories of Rights A right to life, a right to choose; a right to vote, to work, to strike; a right to one phone call, to dissolve parliament, to operate a forklift, to asylum, to equal treatment before the law, to feel proud of what one has done; a right to exist, to sentence an offender to death, to launch a nuclear first strike, to castle kingside, to a distinct genetic identity; a right to believe one's eyes, to pronounce the couple husband and wife, to be left alone, to go to hell in one's own way. We encounter assertions of rights as we encounter sounds: persistently and in great variety. Making sense of this profusion of assertions requires that we class rights together Rby common attributes. Rights-assertions can be categorized, for example, according to: Who is alleged to have the right: Children's rights, animal rights, workers' rights, states' rights, the rights of peoples.